The Journal of Things We Like (Lots)
Select Page

Land Value Capture in the Modern Context

Professor Gerald Korngold has written a useful, thorough, and persuasive argument for the expanded use of land value capture, or LVC. His report is published by the Lincoln Institute of Land Policy, an organization that has long supported the economic work of Henry George.

George argued that real estate investors should profit from the fruits of their own labors but not those of the community. This means that these investors may benefit from the increased value of their improvements and additions to the land but not from land appreciation brought about by external factors. Increases in land value caused by the community should be recaptured by the community.

In the opening section of the report, Professor Korngold defines his terms, noting that “LVC enables communities to recover and reinvest land value increases resulting from public investment and other government actions.” (P. 6.)

For example, if a municipality constructs a subway station that causes neighboring property values to rise, owners should share some of that unearned gain with the public, thereby allowing the community to make further infrastructure investments. More controversially, a community might take a similar approach to regulatory changes that enhance property values, such as upzonings that permit greater density.

Subsequent chapters of the report systematically examine a range of LVC tools. Those arising from infrastructure investments include exactions, impact fees, linkage fees, special assessments, and mandates for inclusionary housing. Landowners who benefit from a municipal project might be required to transfer some of the unearned gain back to the community that paid for these boosts in value.

When regulatory changes benefit an owner, by contrast, the municipality might demand contributions of infrastructure or cash in exchange. For example, an urban owner that receives permission to build above otherwise applicable height limits might be required to fund improvements to a nearby subway station that will be burdened by the increased traffic the enlarged building will attract or might be required to build those improvements itself.

In either case, the community provides a tangible benefit to the landowner that increases the value of the owner’s land, and the owner must reciprocate at least partially. Outcomes such as these are both efficient and fair, as they expand overall land value while internalizing economic externalities. They also provide another funding option for stressed municipalities that desperately need infrastructure enhancements.

There are, of course, impediments and counterarguments. LVC must be permitted by applicable enabling legislation, and some states flat-out prohibit one or more of these devices. LVC can cause cash-flow problems for owners whose increased land value leads to imposition of a tax or other mandatory payment, as they may not have the cash on hand to pay for the augmented value of their land. There are line-drawing problems: How close to the subway station must a lot be for it to be included within the class of beneficiaries? There are also valuation problems, such as how to appraise a required donation of open space for use by the public.

Some landowners view LVC as contrary to their property rights. Several LVC devices raise regulatory takings issues, not all of which have been addressed by the Supreme Court.

Moreover, once LVC contributions arrive, how should they be spent? These payments might be used to benefit the neighborhood immediately surrounding the project, the residents of which may be enduring in-kind costs such as increased density or traffic. Alternatively, the funds might be spent more broadly to enhance equity throughout the community.

Perhaps most important is the question of who should make these decisions. Many land use bodies are subject to capture by real estate interests. Historically under-represented groups may not have a seat at the table when these difficult choices are being debated.

Professor Korngold makes a compelling case for the expanded use of LVC. There are ever-increasing needs for infrastructure. The more the country urbanizes, the greater the demand and need for amenities. As incomes grow, residents expect higher levels of service from their communities. In addition, the expansion of regulations such as environmental laws leads to the need for upgrades.

He notes that ad valorem property taxes indirectly import some aspects of LVC. As a new public project increases land values nearby, assessed valuations increase in tandem, and the owner’s taxes rise as well. But property tax increases are capped in many jurisdictions, in some instances as a direct response to past tax increases that resulted from infrastructure upgrades. “Some would argue that LVC charges for benefited properties should be distinct from the property tax and instead become analogous to a fund for initial capital investments. The property tax could then be used for ongoing operational municipal expenses.” (P. 10.)

One question the work does not directly address is the extent to which it might be wise to mitigate LVC concepts in some circumstances to enhance housing affordability (though it does discuss the use of funds raised in this way to build lower-cost housing elsewhere). The internalization of externalities causes homebuyers to bear the full cost of their homes. This may seem fair – you should pay for what you use – but it elevates housing costs. When might a community forego this type of internalization to reduce home prices?

Whatever the benefits of LVC, perhaps it needs to be balanced against other considerations in cases like these. Professor Korngold makes a compelling case for the wider use of LVC; perhaps a longer work might also examine which settings are best suited to these wider uses.

While this scholarly work is billed as a “Policy Focus Report,” it reads like a law review article. It is thoroughly researched, informative, well-documented, persuasive, and enjoyable to read.

It does differ from a traditional journal article in one regard, though, namely the manner in which it is presented. This report is published in full color, with photographs, drawings, graphs, and tables deployed throughout to illustrate key points. It is laid out in two columns, is broken into small sections, and makes ample use of sidebar comments. All of these features make it far easier to read than the typical journal article and, in many ways, more useful. (Law review editors and online database services, take note!) It thus pairs the academic features of a journal article with the readability of lighter material.

Professor Korngold’s Policy Focus Report is a valuable and thought-provoking addition to the literature. It addresses an old and useful device that might be used more frequently to solve several related municipal problems. To the extent that local leaders are already using this device, Professor Korngold’s report encourages them to expand that use. To the extent that they are not, it inspires them to consider it and to urge state legislatures to allow them to use it more frequently.

Cite as: Gregory M. Stein, Land Value Capture in the Modern Context, JOTWELL (May 17, 2023) (reviewing Gerald Korngold, Land Value Capture in the United States: Funding Infrastructure and Local Government Services (2022)), https://property.jotwell.com/land-value-capture-in-the-modern-context/.

Land Use Deregulation and Affordable Housing

Richard C. Schragger, The Perils of Land Use Deregulation, 170 U. Pa. L. Rev. 125 (2021).

Professor Richard C. Schragger’s article, The Perils of Land Use Deregulation, provides a cautionary tale as to whether land use reform by state legislative preemption will backfire in the attempt to provide more affordable housing. Efforts to address the housing crisis have focused on state preemptive legislation to combat NIMBYism (“Not in My Backyard”) and local land use controls by using market reforms to speak to the perceived housing shortage.

The affordable housing crisis has generated calls for land use reform in response to claims that exclusionary zoning (for example, single-family housing codes and discriminatory practices by localities) exists at the base of this crisis. With the vigorous ongoing debate about the supply-side solution to housing demand, it is not clear whether upzoning, which may reduce market rate housing prices marginally, will produce affordable housing.

State regulation adopting a market-based solution could potentially reduce localities’ power to address economic inequality. Schragger challenges the conventional wisdom, supported by the YIMBY (“Yes in My Backyard”) movement that the state or possibly the federal government should preempt local regulations that interfere with market-rate housing construction.

Recently, some states and localities have targeted single-family zoning as responsible for racial segregation, exclusion of the poor, and lack of affordable housing. For example, California enacted Senate Bill 9, which allows homeowners in single-family zones to add a second unit onto their property or to divide their residential lot into two lots and build up to two housing units on each lot.

With some exceptions, the California law preempts municipal review in order to simplify and expedite the building permit process. And, Minneapolis, Minnesota, eliminated single-family-only zoning in January 2020 to allow building duplexes and triplexes to provide affordable housing. It may be too early to see the impact of these reforms on housing supply and affordability.

It is easy to jump on the “let’s toss zoning” bandwagon because of zoning’s sordid history of explicit racial discrimination and its role in segregating neighborhoods through Euclidean exclusion of apartments from single-family residential zones. Professor Schragger agrees with the criticisms of exclusionary zoning but argues that cities should maintain local power over land use. Cities can address economic inequality by leveraging land use development to obtain higher wage and labor standards, and they can negotiate community benefits agreements (CBAs) with developers.

Many have argued for deconstructing local zoning and municipal power. Professor Schragger’s article contributes mightily to this debate by making sure we consider both sides and proceed with restraint. Professor Christopher Serkin likewise cautioned, in his article, A Case for Zoning,1 that zoning is an important tool in “controlling the pace of community change.”

Schragger reminds us that, historically, populations have shifted from the city core to the suburbs and then back to the city as residents who are mobile chase wealth and opportunity and desert the poor and working class. This leaves some areas with plentiful housing (i.e., Detroit) and others with scarcity (i.e., New York City). Instead, he argues that the city should use its power to pursue economic reform without state law preemption and respond to citizens’ economic and social welfare needs in place.

Urban and suburban land markets may see dynamic change as remote work and increased online learning empty office buildings and classrooms. The demand for particular locations may experience rapid transformation, and statewide legislation will inappropriately deal with housing needs as cities become “newly popular and suburbs stagnate” or vice-versa.

Increasingly, local governments are asked to address challenges that could not be confronted at the state or federal level. Efforts to adapt to climate change have required local land use reforms, given the importance of local decisions permitting building in flood zones, hillsides, coastlines, and the wildlife urban interface (WUI).

In this debate over the proper role of government in providing shelter for our citizens, we need the cautionary voices of Professor Schragger and others to call attention to the city’s importance as the site for participatory and democratic governance and its “power as a potential counterweight to private-side economic domination.” (P. 203.)

  1. Christopher Serkin, A Case for Zoning, 96 Notre Dame L. Rev. 749, 750-52 (2020).
Cite as: Shelley Ross Saxer, Land Use Deregulation and Affordable Housing, JOTWELL (April 21, 2023) (reviewing Richard C. Schragger, The Perils of Land Use Deregulation, 170 U. Pa. L. Rev. 125 (2021)), https://property.jotwell.com/land-use-deregulation-and-affordable-housing/.

Is What Property Is What Property Does?

Christopher Serkin, What Property Does, 75 Vand. L. Rev. 891 (2022).

Law sets the possibilities and reciprocal constraints within which human action can be incentivized, the benefits of exchange can be calculated, and conflicts can be resolved by a neutral arbiter in a predictable way. In these ways, law is operative on behavior. Law is not just a thing to be defined but instead can be defined by what it does.

In What Property Does, Professor Christopher Serkin reveals this insight by studying the services property law provides us for managing our relationships with others and with things. His article shifts the traditional baseline question. As he states, “Instead of asking what property is”—the question fielded in so much of property scholarship—his article “asks what property does.” (P. 893.)

Through dissection of several individual property doctrines, Serkin exposes a common, “underappreciated” purpose in the background of each—“protecting reliance on resources by favoring slow changes over fast ones in the evolution of property rights.” (P. 893.)

Consequently, Serkin’s article aims to explain why “Property, in this view, is a stabilizing but not ossifying force.” (P. 893.) A stable legal system needs the capacity to make durable commitments to those acting within it, but concomitantly should have enough play in its joints to grow slowly to adapt to changing conditions and evolving preferences of the consumers of the law.

Trespass, for example, protects expectations of ownership while adverse possession promotes dynamism. (P. 895.) Accretion and erosion can cause permanent changes in previously recognized property boundaries, but avulsion events like hurricanes, which involve dramatic and rapid shifts in the paths of rivers or shorelines, do not result in recognized changes to legal property lines.

The voluntary exchanges resulting in servitudes generally get protected by property law, but property law also recognizes the changes to property rights that occur by prescriptive easements, waiver, or changed conditions. These changes are justified, Serkin contends, by long time horizons that allow rights to shift only after reliance on the prior agreements becomes arguably unreasonable or not worthy of property law’s protection. Put differently, Serkin seems to conclude that property law does not effectively serve its broader governing purposes when, at best, it only protects anachronistic past reliance.

Among other examples, Serkin also uses his lens to help explain several areas of takings law. For example, while Penn Coal in 1922 held that coal miners were entitled to compensation for regulatory actions that negated clearly-delineated deed rights to mine all their coal, the Keystone Bituminous case sixty-five years later, finding no regulatory taking under a similar set of deeds and a similar regulatory limitation on mining, can be explained if viewed through Serkin’s “evolutionary reliance” lens. Serkin claims that the “[c]oal companies’…reliance had become tempered over time by increasingly restrictive regulations governing” mining. (P. 949.) Serkin calls these changes “accretive shifts” that are not just changes in law but necessarily precipitated by changes in reliance interests.

Serkin examines seemingly distinct doctrines and explains why they are intentionally or spontaneously and evolutionarily ordered to have related but sometimes concealed DNA strands that operate cross-doctrinally. This is an extremely valuable way to find coherence within a legal subject that might otherwise seem like only a collection of disjointed doctrinal parts. By doing so, we can see how doctrines relate, while generating metrics usable across doctrines to evaluate whether any particular doctrine has become aberrant to systemic themes.

That is precisely what Serkin is attempting to do for property law. He contends that his examination shows that property law “has its own internal logic based on protecting people’s reliance on resources in the world,” but that property is best seen as the “locus of competing reliance interests.” (P. 955.)

Further, “reliance…can arise or subside through use or disuse,” and consequently, property law recognizes dynamism in property rights as a consequence of “evolutionary reliance.” (P. 955.) But the property law system does so only in such a way that does not result in dramatic shifts in legal treatment that would themselves undermine the utility of reliance for setting reasonable expectations or allowing property law to aid individuals ordering their lives and investments.

Indeed, the doctrinal developments in property law create rules that “constrain how quickly reliance can change,” without prohibiting or unduly impeding doctrinal changes that help the system adapt to the changing human environment in which the rules operate. (P. 955.) By limiting change to gradual shifts, Serkin contends that property law preserves optimal levels of reliance ensuring that “people are given time to adapt” to changes in law. (P. 897.)

In private ordering protected by neutral arbiters and within a liberal and democratic system, law is supplied in a manner that reflects the demands its consumers place on it. Thus, law reflects the preferences of its consumers. Property law operates no differently.

But Serkin’s work explains that law may evolve as preferences evolve and in ways to accommodate competing demands or preferences too. However, because property law at its heart recognizes the importance of reliance interests, property serves a unique role in regulating the pace of that evolution and in mediating between competing reliance interests.

Notably, Serkin is defending changes that result in recognized alterations to previously-transacted or legally-expected property rights’ assignments. At the same time, Serkin recognizes the critical need for stability in property rights and argues against displacement of property rights by dramatic shifts (at least uncompensated ones) in favor of allowing property law and property rights claims to act as checks on such non-gradual changes.

Thus, he recognizes that “some may worry that focusing on reliance is too protective, and others that it is not protective enough.” (P. 899.) While Serkin then concludes that “adherents of both camps will find much to dislike” in his article, we should instead focus on why all property scholars of any camp should engage with Serkin’s account to refine their own work by thinking more about whether what property is can best be defined by what property does.

Indeed, the first question I ask my students on the first day of my property course each semester has always been “What is property?” Inspired by Professor Serkin, I think I will lead off next semester by asking the students “What does property law do?”

Cite as: Donald Kochan, Is What Property Is What Property Does?, JOTWELL (April 6, 2023) (reviewing Christopher Serkin, What Property Does, 75 Vand. L. Rev. 891 (2022)), https://property.jotwell.com/is-what-property-is-what-property-does/.

The Long Shadow of Statue Statutes

Deborah R. Gerhardt, Law in the Shadows of Confederate Monuments, 27 Mich. J. Race & L. 1 (2021).

In recent years, communities across the United States have accelerated decisions to remove Confederate monuments. Many removals have been successfully completed with the cooperation of the property owner and public authorities. But others, especially in Southern states, have been more challenging. In nine states, “statue statutes” can prevent or inhibit any changes to Confederate monuments, even where the property owner (often, a local government) seeks removal.

Deborah R. Gerhardt’s Law in the Shadows of Confederate Monuments presents an enriching account of the tensions created by state statue statutes, and it offers a new idea to resolve them.

At the outset, Gerhardt characterizes these laws as “‘preservation’ laws,” rightly using quotation marks to signal that they sit outside of what preservation law is normally thought to encompass. Their drafters have tried to coopt preservation terminology, giving statue statutes titles like “memorial preservation,” “cultural heritage,” and “memorial protection.”

But in fact, established preservation laws reject the notion that a specific history or time period be given special treatment – or even that the statues are protectable to begin with. Normally, only those places deemed to satisfy broad, public criteria evaluating their significance and their material integrity will be protected. In virtually all cases, designation criteria exclude commemorative works that merely memorialize some prior event or historical figure. The rationale for this exclusion is that commemorative works are not themselves historic, but rather interpret history. Statue statutes’ protection for a narrow category of commemorative works thus runs contrary to established preservation law.

That said, the argument for protecting these statutes has some basis in international cultural heritage norms. Gerhardt notes a global inclination disfavoring destruction, reminding readers of the international outcry that met the looting of the Baghdad Museum and the destruction of temples in Syria, among other events.

But, as she explains, American Confederate monuments differ from these other cultural artifacts. She argues that Confederate monuments “amplify a message of legal inequality…[and] impose constant reminders of the nation’s refusal to confront systemic racism.” (P. 16.) She cites to research explaining how the exaltation of Lost Cause ideology has negative health consequences, primarily psychological harm.

Given that context, Gerhardt argues, Confederate monuments deserve greater scrutiny. And yet, in nine states, these monuments have earned greater protection.

The article deftly leads the reader through the legal issues raised by statue statutes, logging the variety of ways in which communities have tried to smooth the removal process. It gives full treatment to the highly-publicized debate in Richmond, Virginia, which resulted in the city’s removal of several prominent statues on Monuments Avenue after modifications to the Virginia statue statute. In Tennessee, the City of Memphis sold the land on which one of its Confederate monuments stood to a private party, circumventing the state law that, at the time, only prohibited monument removal on public land.

Additionally, a county in North Carolina reviewed historical property records to successfully argue that a Confederate statue sitting on public property stood subject to a revocable license. The City of New Orleans received a court order declaring several public statues to be public nuisances, given the psychological harm they imposed on the city’s majority-Black residents. Other towns have invoked the public nuisance theory, too, though not always successfully, as Emily Behzadi’s recent article chronicles.

Both anti-statue local governments and pro-statue groups have also, largely unsuccessfully, raised First Amendment challenges. For example, courts rejected arguments from Lakeland, Florida, and Birmingham, Alabama, that statue statutes infringed on local-government speech. They have also rejected Confederate sympathizers’ First Amendment claims because their allegiance to the Lost Cause cannot be considered speech.

Of the various examples included in the article highlighting the fraught legal landscape, the one that stuck with me most was Gerhardt’s fascinating account of the tug-of-war over the “Silent Sam” statue on the campus of her institution, the University of North Carolina. The war ultimately ended in the statue’s removal, but not without several lawsuits, student arrests, and the resignation of the chancellor. That account underscores the need for guidance outside of the current state-local framework for making decisions about monuments.

Gerhardt focuses her search for such guidance on federal laws that could be interpreted to preempt state statue statutes. The article considers, then rejects established federal historic preservation laws, including the National Historic Preservation Act, as possible frameworks for mediating disputes. These laws impose obligations on federal agencies to consider historic resources in making decisions and do not address non-historic commemorative works nor offer guidance for resolving non-federal issues. The article also evaluates, then dismisses the power of federal copyright law to support monument retention, given that many monuments were factory-made and that any artists’ rights to protect their artistic works from demolition have long expired.

Instead, the article proposes that the federal Civil Rights Act of 1964 be considered a vehicle for challenging existing monuments. Among other things, the Act prohibits race-based and color-based exclusion from participation in programs receiving federal assistance, and it prohibits race-based and color-based discrimination. The Act enables private parties to claim a racially hostile environment, and caselaw interpreting the Act confirms that visual imagery can contribute to a racially hostile environment.

The article succinctly explains how a legal theory based on the Act might be treated by a court. Like the recent public nuisance suits, a Civil Rights Act suit would focus on the impact of the monuments. Additional research on such impacts may be needed to better support the claim, but I give Gerhardt credit for advancing a novel idea.

I will close by noting that this area of scholarship has been active. Over the last few years, legal scholars have published over a dozen articles (and students a half-dozen more) about Confederate monuments. Please give them a look. And for a reader interested in an expanded, non-law-review treatment of these issues, I highly recommend Erin L. Thompson’s book, Smashing Statues: The Rise and Fall of America’s Public Monuments.

Note: This Jot was written and submitted before Professor Bronin’s public service leave from Cornell University, and it does not represent an official statement by or constitute an official publication of the U.S. Advisory Council on Historic Preservation.

Cite as: Sara Bronin, The Long Shadow of Statue Statutes, JOTWELL (March 7, 2023) (reviewing Deborah R. Gerhardt, Law in the Shadows of Confederate Monuments, 27 Mich. J. Race & L. 1 (2021)), https://property.jotwell.com/the-long-shadow-of-statue-statutes/.

Reconfiguring the Escape Rooms for a Clearer Path to Takings

Lee Anne Fennell, Escape Room: Implicit Takings After Cedar Point Nursery, 17 Duke J. of Const. L. & Pub. Pol’y 1 (2022).

As Professor M. Carol Rose so famously wrote years ago, the law of property is about “crystals and mud.”1 In Professor Lee Anne Fennell’s view, there is perhaps no muddier area than the law of takings, and made even more so by Cedar Point Nursery v. Hassid, 141 S. Ct. 2063 (2021).

In this 2021 case, the U.S. Supreme Court ruled that a state regulation that gave union organizers access to agricultural worksites for up to three hours per day for 120 days per year, effected a per se taking by physical invasion. Just as we thought we had understood the broad types of takings, according to Professor Fennell, the Court devised “a new per se takings contraption…throwing physical impositions on owners into it wholesale, along with bewildering means of possible extrication.” (P. 3.)

Prof. Fennell states that “implicit takings,” those that are not the result of eminent domain proceedings, “has now effectively become an escape room—a gratuitously convoluted analytic environment, filled with many traps and puzzles.” (Pp. 3-4) This scheme, in her view, is a device for mischief—disfavored impositions on owners, wealth-disturbing impacts, can be checked, while wealth-enhancing measures, such as zoning may be allowed. But it does this only by making categories that are murky.

Prof. Fennell’s recounting of the road leading to Cedar Point reveals a twisted path, since that case doesn’t seem to fit neatly into the deprivation of all value framework of Lucas, the permanent physical occupation of Loretto, or the Penn Central balancing scheme.

Using the analogy of a board game, she describes the escape room as consisting of two doors: one involving claims regarding physical access, the other involving use limitations. Thanks to the mud tracked in by Cedar Point, even as we enter one room, we still do not know for sure what rules will apply—whether there is a per se taking or something else. This complication arises because of the great variety of claimants who might be in that room—from labor organizers to seeing eye dogs, who, although not property owners, may present worthy claims to access.

Prof. Fennell notes that the Court has expressly articulated exceptions to takings theory, but they are not always clear cut. First, there is the open door, i.e., where the landowner has invited the public in, but for what purpose? To shop or to distribute leaflets? Are there tenants with rights and guests? Is there a need to offer medical treatment to occupiers? Fennell wonders whether required open doors (for safety on construction sites and against discrimination) might also be covered by analogy.

Then there are the isolated physical intrusions that do not rise to the level of a taking. Finally, there are the background principles, but do these include labor laws? Anti-discrimination laws? Health and safety regulations? Do they vary by state? If trying to discern whether a government act triggers per se jurisprudence or the Penn Central balancing was not hard enough, once we move to exactions, the law becomes even more muddled.

Before Cedar Point, governments did not need to bargain for every entry necessary to carry out a regulatory program. Cedar Point suggests that inspections can easily pass Nollan and Dolan, then asserts in the same breath that the union access requirement could never pass muster because it does not involve a government benefit that can be “h[e]ld hostage.” If governments must now resort to bargains with landowners in order to govern, the societal costs of living with laws rises significantly.

The Cedar Point Court seemed to assign absolute priority to the right to exclude and imply that the only opening for Penn Central is in the initial characterization of the government action as a physical invasion or use limit, which in itself is not a simple proposition. On this score, it is hard to distinguish Pruneyard from Cedar Point.

Prof. Fennell sees physical intrusion as less relevant, since all regulations have physical manifestations to some degree, even if entry happens only to determine whether the law is being followed. In Prof. Fennell’s view, Cedar Point was the next step in the progression of giving heightened scrutiny to regulations impacting property rights—but not all such regulations, only selective ones. But what is the purpose of this new device?

Fennell believes the purpose of this new scrutiny is toward the preservation of the wealth structure in society. This means that certain uses and requirements that are necessary for larger society ends may need to fall in favor of preserving a landowner’s domain.

She develops a new taxonomy to help guide students (not just law students but students of the subject). In this ordering, some acts are entitled to no takings scrutiny (government acts that are not legitimate or that merely instantiates background principles); some should be subject to low scrutiny (for use restrictions that do not fall into Cedar Point’s per se mold); exactions should be given a heightened level of scrutiny, thereby removing some land use restrictions from bargain-making altogether if the uses in question are too “basic and familiar” to require anything in exchange—they will just be takings. Alleged per se takings should be subject to “infinitely high scrutiny.”

The last part of the paper focuses on the nagging question of what compensation is owed—the value of the space occupied by the government or the value of the whole property if we find a per se taking.

Professor Fennell admits that even her very inventive taxonomy may not be capable of separating crystals in the mud. While property gives autonomy and security and encourages investment, we should keep in our minds the resonating words of Morris Cohen, in Property and Sovereignty,2 that “dominion over things is also imperium over our fellow human beings.” The Cedar Point Court apparently did not see the agricultural workers laboring in the background.

  1. Carol M. Rose, Crystals and Mud in Property Law, 40 Stan. L. Rev. 577 (1988).
  2. 13 Cornell L. Rev. 8 (1927).
Cite as: Shelby D. Green, Reconfiguring the Escape Rooms for a Clearer Path to Takings, JOTWELL (February 21, 2023) (reviewing Lee Anne Fennell, Escape Room: Implicit Takings After Cedar Point Nursery, 17 Duke J. of Const. L. & Pub. Pol’y 1 (2022)), https://property.jotwell.com/reconfiguring-the-escape-rooms-for-a-clearer-path-to-takings/.

Property through a Propriety Lens: Servitudes as American Matryoshkii (Russian Dolls)

Elizabeth Elia, Servitudes Done “Proper”ly: Propriety, Not Contract Law, __ J. Land Use & Envtl. L. __ (forthcoming), available at SSRN.

One of my favorite souvenirs from studying and working in Russia is a many-layered matryoshka, or “Russian Doll.” The unpretentious red, yellow, and blue painted wooden doll opens to reveal a smaller, nearly identical doll, which in turn opens to reveal another and another. This particular matryoshka has eleven dolls nested within one another – the smallest barely larger than a grain of rice.

How delightful it was to read Elizabeth Elia’s article, Servitudes Done “Proper”ly: Propriety, Not Contract Law, which frames community servitudes as one of the many nested governing layers within our legal system. Elia’s “Russian Doll” metaphor is compelling, and her broader point – that a governance (“propriety”) frame is the appropriate one for property law – provides gratifying and unexpected analytical clarity to the law of servitudes.

Courts and scholars struggle to make sense of today’s new uses of servitudes that diverge both in form and function from traditional servitudes. For example, the continuing relevance of certain common law requirements, including horizontal privity, has been called into question by the controversial Restatement of Property (Third): Servitudes.

Although many courts still claim that covenants will only run with the land if they “touch and concern” it, the concept of touch and concern is so elastic as to seem based on the eye of the beholder. Common interest communities (CICs) are today created through recorded declarations that conveniently skirt the common law mandate of separate ownership for burdened and benefitted parcels as well as, perhaps, its prohibition of covenants in gross.

In spite of their uneasy fit within traditional servitude rules, CIC covenants – along with conservation easements, affordability covenants, and other quasi-zoning types of modern servitudes – are almost universally enforced by courts.

Enforcement has involved awkwardly stretching (or simply ignoring) traditional servitude law, although modernly, enforcement is more easily facilitated by a plethora of enabling statutes – for CICs and conservation easements in particular. Where specific enabling legislation is lacking, courts simply analyze these restrictions under the auspices of government authority (for example, affordability covenants) or contract law (for example, agreements between developers and local zoning authorities). But still, all such constructs are, at bottom, servitudes on land.

Without a unifying analytical framework, the apparent haphazard judicial treatment of such restrictions has made modern servitude law frustrating to navigate.

For decades, scholars have tried to make sense of this confusion. Richard Epstein, for example, argues that freedom of contract principles, rather than ancient servitude law, should guide legal analysis of easements and covenants today.1 On the other hand, Carol Rose points out that different justifications for property law may drive different judicial approaches to servitudes.2 Rose distinguishes a preference satisfaction justification (grounded in liberal economic theory) from the more ancient justification for property, grounded in the need to promote order and well-being for the people (a concept she calls propriety). Elia synthesizes servitude law using the lens of propriety but argues that governance in liberal democracies incorporate preference satisfaction as a tool for voluntary compliance with the law.

According to Elia, property is properly viewed as nested systems of governance – police power of the state (sometimes devolved to localities) and police power of the individual (sometimes alienated to a manager). The propriety frame casts private property as existing in order to allocate governing power.

Elia explains that the Blackstonian “dominion” of private property is all about governance and governors – usually existing in nested frameworks of overlapping authority and responsibility. “Traditional servitudes” among two parties/parcels impair governance and are disfavored by traditional common law; but “community servitudes” facilitate governance and are therefore favored by courts and legislatures. Such “community servitudes” coordinate uses of land for the mutual benefit of the people, land, and things in the community. Because community servitudes function as neighborhood governance, they are more properly constrained by due process concerns rather than by traditional servitude formation formalities.

Elia’s Servitudes Done “Proper”ly article adds much value to property scholarship. Here are my five favorite things about the article:

  • Elia’s propriety frame pushes back on the purely contractual approach to property law – an approach which is problematic because (a) property is distinct from contracts in terms of its scope, application, and remedies, and (b) treating servitudes as contracts risks having consumer contract law’s voluntariness problem spread to restrictions on land.
  • Elia’s analytical frame not only brings a desperately needed clarity to servitude law but may also provide a comprehensible approach to other muddied areas of modern property jurisprudence – like regulatory takings law.
  • Elia shatters the public-private binary that hobbles the law of land use and ignores the quasi-public nature of private land use restrictions, paving the way for productive consideration of checks on private governance (for example, a homeowners’ bill of rights for CICs or intergenerational justice constraints for conservation easements).
  • Elia’s recognition that governance of land and people is a multi-layered “Russian Doll” enriches the federalism debate animating many areas of the law today and highlights that not only is the “who decides?” question paramount, but also that it may be answered in a non-exclusive and lawfully constrained way.
  • The property-as-police power lens that incorporates a preference satisfaction justification reanimates questions of property responsibilities that arise from the trust-like role of a governing authority, providing a more solid foundation upon which principles of progressive property can build.

Viewed through Elia’s propriety lens, the law of servitudes becomes more cohesive, comprehensible, and consistent; the relationship between property and stewardship becomes more apparent; and the justification for governance limits – to ensure both personal freedom and public welfare – is more compelling. Nesting individual preferences within the concept of the community and the state, all painted with the patina of property rights and obligations, crafts an elegant American solution to the “Russian Doll” governance complexity our legal system is grappling with today.

  1. Richard Epstein, Notice and Freedom of Contract in the Law of Servitudes, 55. S. Cal. L. Rev. 1353 (1981).
  2. Carol M. Rose, Property as Wealth, Property as Propriety, Compensatory Justice: Nomos XXXIII 223 (John W. Chapman ed., 1991).
Cite as: Andrea Boyack, Property through a Propriety Lens: Servitudes as American Matryoshkii (Russian Dolls), JOTWELL (February 3, 2023) (reviewing Elizabeth Elia, Servitudes Done “Proper”ly: Propriety, Not Contract Law, __ J. Land Use & Envtl. L. __ (forthcoming), available at SSRN), https://property.jotwell.com/property-through-a-propriety-lens-servitudes-as-american-matryoshkii-russian-dolls/.

Owning (Up To) the Climate Crisis

Rashmi Dyal-Chand, Sharing the Climate, 122 Colum. L. Rev. 581 (2022).

Sharing the Climate by Professor Rashmi Dyal-Chand shines a light on a surprisingly understudied, yet immensely important, aspect of the climate crisis: to a large extent, the climate crisis is all about resources. Whether fertile and livable land, healthy trees, drinkable water or breathable air, the depletion starts with resource management (or, failures thereof).

Property is the conceptual category that allows us to distribute and govern resources. So property law and concepts should be at the forefront of responding to a resource-based crisis, right? As Rashmi Dyal-Chand points out, unfortunately, at the moment, that is not the case.

The key contribution of the article is underscoring the ways in which property law could contribute to the climate discourse. Dyal-Chand calls on scholars and policymakers to examine the role property law currently plays, and the role it can play, in mitigating and adapting to the climate crisis.

This call is two-fold: first, it calls on the broader climate community to examine how property law can be part of the set of solutions offered. Given the crisis is one of resource management, if we are to mitigate the vexing climate issues and imagine a future that preserves the long-term viability of our resources, property must be part of the solution. Property law also addresses an aspect that is generally not covered by other types of climate responses – the relationship between neighbors within the community. It is significant as a response to the crisis for that reason as well.

Second, the article calls on property law scholars to examine how property law can adapt to the reality of a changing climate. “It is imperative for property law,” she underscores, “to develop durable, systemic response to the climate crisis.” This is key to maintaining a viable and vibrant environment, but also is crucial for the utility and durability of property law itself.

On that front, Dyal-Chand suggests an expansion of the law of neighbors, and the establishment of more access-focused regimes. Building on the ability of close-knit communities to work cooperatively, this is essentially an exercise in reimagining rights of access, such that certain activities, which are necessary for climate adaptation and mitigation, could be facilitated rather than prohibited.

This is both normatively and pragmatically significant. The everyday life of landownership, as Dyal-Chand reminds us, is largely premised on separatism, in different forms. Normatively, this is true whether one takes a utilitarian-based stance, or an autonomy-based one. Either way, the core commitment seems to be rooted in the exclusionary, every-person-to-their-own kind of intuition. While this kind of dynamic is suited for some contexts and certain eras, it is ill adapted to a world that is rapidly changing and where resources, generally, cut across more than one plot of land and their impact extends beyond the scope of one particular plot.

Property’s response should be, according to Dyal-Chand, creating a sharing-oriented management regime, specifically between neighbors (broadly understood, also encompassing a wider set of community members). “Sharing”, in this context, doesn’t mean that landowners will lose all control over their land nor the ability to enjoy it. It just means that we could allow simultaneous uses of some bits and particular aspects of resources.

Examples could include allowing a neighbor access to sunlight, wind, or a roof space for the purpose of energy production or for facilitating microgrids; or sharing parking spaces in an effort to reduce paved areas and make more room for green parks. It could also include creating linear drainage canals along the edges of multiple parcels, which could help deal with increasing floodwaters; or creating fire-safety corridors through multiple plots that could help mitigate wildfires or act as escape routes for residents.

This kind of regime would have two important advantages. First, by effectively “pooling” bits of resources that are currently split among landowners, the proposed regime better addresses widespread externalities that impact all neighbors (or the neighborhood). Think, for example, how creating a linear drainage canal, on private lands, can benefit all the residents in times of increased floods.

Second, the proposed regime could mitigate the separatism that currently tends to dominate our landownership dynamics, and instead encourage – or rather demand – a more collaborative and deliberative dynamic. This, in turn, has the potential not only to solve the immediate management problem but to entrench a dynamic that will mitigate separatism moving forward.

Whether framed in terms of easements, zoning provisions or otherwise, the idea is that these kinds of pooled and simultaneous uses would not only facilitate more efficient and more climate-friendly use, but importantly, also bolster the social structures which in themselves are important for successfully responding to the climate crisis.

Basically, it turns out that being kind to thy neighbor is a good idea on many fronts; and who knows, beyond mending our shared fences, it might also help us better adapt to the climate crisis.

Cite as: Yael Lifshitz, Owning (Up To) the Climate Crisis, JOTWELL (January 9, 2023) (reviewing Rashmi Dyal-Chand, Sharing the Climate, 122 Colum. L. Rev. 581 (2022)), https://property.jotwell.com/owning-up-to-the-climate-crisis/.

Who Controls the Sidewalks?

Michael Pollack, Sidewalk Government (Aug. 23, 2022), available in draft at SSRN.

In his forthcoming article, Sidewalk Government, Michael Pollack explores the nature and governance of sidewalks in the U.S. through both a property law and local government lens. While most of us have likely used a sidewalk to get from one place to another, we often don’t think about the many complex ways that localities govern these critical spaces.

When I moved to Maine over a decade ago, I was surprised to learn that I was personally responsible for shoveling snow off the sidewalk in front of my house. A few years later, the city expanded the boundaries of the downtown Business Improvement District (“BID”) to cover the other side of my street, after which my across-the-street neighbors no longer had to shovel; the BID did it for them.

More recently, when I moved to Denver, I learned that I would be responsible not only for snow shoveling, but also for replacing the big, expensive, red flagstone slabs that made up the sidewalks in my historic neighborhood if they were to become cracked. Yet in Maine, the city was responsible for fixing tripping hazards on the brick sidewalk in front of my house.

Pollack’s work explores sidewalks as contested spaces. They are sites of conflict regarding ownership, management, and use. The pandemic has made this fact even more evident. In the face of restrictions on indoor dining, many cities moved to expand outdoor seating to allow restaurants and bars to stay in business, and to allow people to congregate more safely.

Although al fresco dining has long been the norm in some cities (and throughout much of the world), cities began to liberalize their permitting and fee requirements, and loosened restrictions on the construction of shelters to protect diners from rain and cold. And while patrons of those establishments often relished the changes, neighbors complained of noise and trash, and others struggled to walk or pass by these tables with enough space to socially distance or fit a wheelchair.

Pollack begins by describing various competing sidewalk users and uses, and he describes the ways that they are often in conflict with each other. He notes that the law surrounding sidewalks is often designed to prioritize moving people from place to place—what Nick Blomley has called “pedestrianism” in his great book about sidewalks.1

But, of course, pedestrians are only a small set of sidewalk users. Pollack also discusses: residents of the neighborhood (both housed and unhoused) who use the sidewalk as an extension of their living space; property owners and lessees who use the sidewalk for commercial purposes or to otherwise benefit their ownership; non-owner commercial interests like vendors, buskers, and rental bikes and scooters; communities gathering together for events, protests, or activism; and governments and utilities that use sidewalks for infrastructure. He notes that the law has not evolved to address the varied conflicts that arise between these competing users.

Pollack then discusses different ways that cities could ameliorate the conflicts that occur on sidewalks, which he likens to common pool resources. He sets aside regulation through norms, given that the uses and users of sidewalks are so disparate and often not close-knit.

He then turns to the role of property law and public regulation and suggests that both have failed thus far. This is in part because of the way that municipal laws tend to place responsibility for sidewalks on abutting property owners, although the sidewalks themselves are publicly owned (or at least subject to an easement for public use).

Abutters are often the ones who must shovel snow or repair broken sidewalks, and in some instances, they are even held liable for injuries that occur on these ostensibly public sidewalks. Although this outsourcing arrangement might be convenient for cities, it’s not necessarily an efficient way to run a city. Further, it often results in the unequal provision of quality, usable sidewalks.

Thus, the laws governing sidewalks have muddled the rights and obligations of both the public and the private. Because of the lack of clear boundaries, sidewalks are akin to liminal spaces where conflict is more likely to arise.2

Although local government regulation can often remedy conflicts in cities when default property rules fail, it too has failed in the context of sidewalks.

The specific problem that Pollack identifies is that the governance of sidewalks in most localities is highly fragmented. While the local department of transportation might be responsible for some uses and users, the planning department, parks department, or consumer affairs department might be responsible for other aspects of sidewalk management, permitting, and control. This uncoordinated governance creates inefficiencies and makes it hard for users to navigate and obtain needed permits or approvals, or to submit complaints.

The solution to the problem of the sidewalks, Pollack suggests, lies in the fact that no one owns them. Thus, we should consider either privatizing these commons, or governing them.

He examines but rejects the idea of actually giving the full bundle of sticks to sidewalk abutters and restauranteurs (although he is open to some level of BID participation). Rather, he settles on the need to “enhance[], streamline[], coordinate[], and consolidate[]” our municipal regulatory architecture. His suggestion to achieve this end involves moving sidewalk maintenance obligations from individual abutters to the municipality itself, and the creation of a unified Department of Sidewalks.

Many cities are making their pandemic-era sidewalk dining expansions permanent. Delivery robots are beginning to make their way down sidewalks alongside people using wheelchairs and others pushing strollers. And with the effects of climate change worsening, cities will be looking to municipal property, including sidewalks, to build bioswales.

The competition for space on sidewalks is only increasing. As we enter this new era, Pollack’s suggestions should lead to less chaotic spaces that work for the whole panoply of sidewalk users.

  1. Nicholas Blomley, Rights of Passage: Sidewalks and the Regulation of Public Flow (2011).
  2. Sarah Schindler, Reconsidering the Strength of the Boundary Line, JOTWELL (October 21, 2019) (reviewing David A. Dana & Nadav Shoked, Property’s Edges, 60 B.C. L. Rev. 753 (2019)), https://property.jotwell.com/reconsidering-the-strength-of-the-boundary-line/.
Cite as: Sarah Schindler, Who Controls the Sidewalks?, JOTWELL (November 23, 2022) (reviewing Michael Pollack, Sidewalk Government (Aug. 23, 2022), available in draft at SSRN), https://property.jotwell.com/who-controls-the-sidewalks/.

Illustrating Rent: Why Is the Tenant Falling?

Sarah Schindler & Kellen Zale, The Anti-Tenancy Doctrine, 171 U. Pa. L. Rev. __ (forthcoming 2023), available at SSRN.

In their forthcoming article, The Anti-Tenancy Doctrine, Sarah Schindler and Kellen Zale proclaim, “The law has failed tenants.” The authors then provide solid evidence of that failure and identify a concept they call the Anti-Tenancy Doctrine.

On Sundays, I treat myself to newspapers, to actual printed newspapers. I make a cup of tea, sit at the table, take a sip, and read the printed word. If I have a copy of The New York Times, I usually read the real estate section first, if only to drool over photos of homes that I cannot afford.

On a recent Sunday, however, the paper published a special issue on renting in the real estate section. The graphic for the first page of the section caught my attention—it pictured a person dressed in yellow and black who appears to be falling into a series of rotating black boxes outlined in a red “For Rent” sign at the bottom.

As a property professor, I wondered what this graphic represented about renting and about our beliefs about renters. Was renting a fall into a deep dark hole? What caused the tenant to fall into that hole, into that abyss? Didn’t the law offer protection from falling into that hole?

Professor Schindler and Zale provide some answers to the questions raised by that illustration. Their article surveys various areas of the law that differentiate between a renter and a homeowner when determining a party’s legal rights. Those differences are often made without any consideration of whether a distinction should exist, leading to anti-tenancy bias.

Professor Schindler and Professor Zale look at this anti-tenant bias in areas of constitutional law, housing law, public safety law, consumer protection and contract law, and tax law. They cover a wide array of topics, from Fourth Amendment searches to Fifth Amendment eminent domain compensation, from disaster relief to credit reporting systems, and from voting rights in common interest communities to voter registration outreach.

Some of the specific examples are familiar such as the mortgage interest deduction. Other examples have received less consideration as being anti-tenant, such as notice requirements in zoning ordinances. Homeowners are usually required to receive notice of proposed zoning changes and an invitation to attend public hearings; tenants, however, are seldom required to be notified even when they may be similarly impacted by the zoning change.

When these seemingly unrelated practices and policies are threaded together, it is hard not to agree with their conclusion that an anti-tenancy bias exists in the law and with their recognition of an Anti-Tenancy Doctrine.

Professor Schindler and Professor Zale then begin to answer the question of why renters and owners are treated differently. They identify five distinct causes: 1) classism; 2) racism; 3) consumerism; 4) NIMBYism; and 5) the influence of classical liberalism.

They begin with a discussion that should be familiar to all first-year property law students–the freeholder/non-freeholder distinction that dates back to feudal England. The authors ask us “to interrogate the common law’s assumption that a leasehold interest is ‘lesser than’ a freehold interest.” They briefly consider the other causes, reminding us how tenancy is often used as a proxy for race and how homeownership is considered a civic virtue, but rentership is not.

The article ends with an invitation to dialogue about how to respond to anti-tenancy and with suggestions for future scholarship on the Anti-Tenancy Doctrine. The authors distinguish between developing solutions that elevate the status of tenants and those that help tenants become homeowners. For many, homeownership is not an option. Thus, we will need to shift our thinking about rentership and homeownership to ensure that housing status is not the determinant of legal rights.

As I read the article, I realized that this dialogue on the inequities caused by Anti-Tenancy Doctrine and possible solutions could easily begin in the first-year property course. Property professors can thread the discussion of why renters and homeowners are treated differently (and whether they should be) not only when covering the topic of landlord/tenant law, but also when teaching topics such as estates and future interests, zoning, and restrictive covenants. Such discussions could provide a unifying framework for topics that students often struggle to relate to one another.

That dialogue could also lead to a different graphic the next time The New York Times decides to publish a special edition on renting. Maybe instead of a figure falling into a series of black boxes, the artist could illustrate the concept of renting with a simple graphic of a renter enjoying a home and shelter protected by law.

Cite as: Serena Williams, Illustrating Rent: Why Is the Tenant Falling?, JOTWELL (October 21, 2022) (reviewing Sarah Schindler & Kellen Zale, The Anti-Tenancy Doctrine, 171 U. Pa. L. Rev. __ (forthcoming 2023), available at SSRN), https://property.jotwell.com/illustrating-rent-why-is-the-tenant-falling/.

Flexible Property Rights and the Resilient State

Professors Marc L. Roark and Lorna Fox O’Mahony’s article, Comparative Property Law and the Pandemic succeeds in bringing property theory and vulnerability theory into conversation and does so in a way that is likely to make vulnerability theory more palatable for property scholars.

Early on, Roark and Fox O’Mahony introduce readers to vulnerability theory. The basic idea of vulnerability theory is that vulnerability is an inherent part of the human condition and that the state should be active in providing people the tools they need to be resilient.

The theory is the brainchild of Professor Martha Fineman. Emory University School of Law’s vulnerability theory project, led by Fineman, regularly hosts or helps organize vulnerability-themed conferences around the world. Although Roark and Fox O’Mahony do not focus on this, by insisting on the universality of vulnerability and trying to break from of labels such as victim and oppressor, vulnerability theory is somewhat at odds with or at least awkwardly positioned next to race or identity-centered theories of the law and of history.

Comparative Property Law and the Pandemic deals with this by focusing less on vulnerability and more on its corollary, resilience. It is a smart move, allowing the authors to not get bogged down in defending vulnerability theory’s claim of universality and instead focus on the details of state responses to property challenges associated with the COVID crisis.

Throughout the article, Roark and Fox O’Mahony introduce and build what they call the Resilient Property Theory, which focuses on both the state’s responsibility towards people and the state’s own vulnerability and corresponding need to be resilient.

Vulnerability theory has captured the hearts and minds of quite a few academics and the growing vulnerability theory literature attests to its power, especially among those whose work focuses on subordination and inequality. But until this article, there had not been a full-throated celebration and elaboration of the theory within the property law space.

Roark and Fox O’Mahony’s article is worth reading, if for no other reason than because it begins, in Part II, a vulnerability theory – property theory conversation.

That said, the more granular case study of state responses to housing vulnerability connected to the COVID epidemic found in Part III, is also worthy of attention. The authors focus on how states, in response to COVID, provided emergency financial relief, employed housing first strategies, and protected (temporarily) tenants from eviction. They argue that the epidemic shifted the range of the politically possible—what they call the Overton window, the range of politically legitimate options at any given time—so that even neoliberal states acted to shelter and protect those “sleeping rough” as well as those who otherwise would be evicted.

Part III’s strength can be found in the way it pulls examples from across jurisdictions; while the focus is primarily on what happened within the United States, the examples of how other nations dealt with housing precarity in COVID’s wake are woven into the larger story beautifully. Readers are shown some of the differences in approaches across countries. But what comes across more are the commonalities. Governments felt that something had to be done and that people within their territories recognized the imperative to help those in need and expected governments to act. A state that failed to act would itself be vulnerable. Put differently, part of the state’s resiliency depended upon a willingness to be both proactive and flexible in a time of crisis.

Roark and Fox O’Mahony are not the first to observe that moments of crisis are also moments of opportunity; the Article draws upon prior work by Professors Nestor Davidson and Rashmi Dyal-Chand when discussing such opportunities.

As Comparative Property Law and the Pandemic highlights, many of the protections extended by the state—whether in terms of financial assistance or eviction bans—were, by design, temporary. The same arguably is true of the political space to help those in need: things going back to normal could cause a retreat to the neoliberal default of blaming the poor and protecting property owners. Such a retreat itself would arguably fit within Resilient Property Theory’s framework if the state felt it had to move in such a direction to shore up its own strength.

The article does not answer the question of whether Resilient Property Theory tends towards social inclusion or exclusion, but it is clear from the authors’ presentation that state resilience is highly contextual and more flexible than would be predicted by high theory absolutist claims.

Though this review is a celebration of their article, it is worth noting that the article gives a taste of the larger and more in-depth coverage of many of the same issues that are found in their recently published book—Lorna Fox O’Mahony & Marc L. Roark, Squatting and the State: Resilient Property in an Age of Crisis (2022).

For people interested in comparative property law and a fuller elaboration of Resilient Property Theory, the book is well worth checking out. But for those intimidated by the book’s four hundred plus pages and its detailed property histories of multiple nations, the article does a good job promoting a vulnerability theory approach to property.

Indeed, by moving from an emphasis on vulnerability to speaking primarily in terms of resilience, I would argue, Roark and Fox O’Mahony improve upon the theory and make it more likely that it finds a theoretical home within the diverse landscape that is property theory.

Cite as: Ezra Rosser, Flexible Property Rights and the Resilient State, JOTWELL (September 22, 2022) (reviewing Marc L. Roark & Lorna Fox O’Mahony, Comparative Property Law and the Pandemic: Vulnerability Theory and Resilient Property in an Age of Crises, 82 La. L. Rev. 789 (2022)), https://property.jotwell.com/flexible-property-rights-and-the-resilient-state/.